February 20, 2010
Caring about the Parthenon Sculptures for the right reasons
Constantine Sandis looks back at the issue of the Parthenon Sculptures following the opening of the New Acropolis Museum. The New Acropolis Museum is compared to the British Museum’s concept of the universal museum, showing that both museums exhibit universalism, but in different forms. More importantly though, he asks whether both sides have lost site of the true issue of what is best for the sculptures.
From:
The Liberal
The New Acropolis
by Constantine SandisDull is the eye that will not weep to see
Thy walls defaced, thy mouldering shrines removed
By British hands, which it had best behoved,
To guard those relics ne’er to be restored.
Lord Byron, Childe Harold’s Pilgrimage, Canto XV, 3-6.Last summer, the New Acropolis Museum in Athens opened its gates, not only to the public but also to a flood of arguments and emotions old and new. The root cause of this commotion lies in the fact that nearly half of the sculptures which originally graced the Parthenon have been residing in the British Museum, ever since they were purchased from the bankrupt Lord Elgin in 1816. Numerous smaller fragments, it is often forgotten, are kept by other museums across Europe.
It is difficult to judge whether Elgin – who removed the pieces under contested legal circumstances when Athens was under Ottoman rule – ultimately did more to save or to damage the marbles, and no easier to tell whether he was acting out of greed or preservationist foresight. What is clear is that, while the original Acropolis museum (established in 1865) was never capable of adequately housing the site’s antiquities, and the British Museum’s current display of the sculptures in its possession remains poor, the New Acropolis Museum has been specifically designed to display all of the sculptures, including those held in London. (These are currently represented by unpatinated plaster casts acquired from the British Museum in 1840). Whatever the historical and counterfactual details may be, the time is now ripe for all surviving sculptures to be reunited under one roof.This claim has been contested by the trustees of the British Museum and many others, such as James Cuneo of the Chicago Institute of Art, who defend the universalist position that it is only in large international museums can historical art and craft be appreciated and understood in the full context of both the (earlier) cultures that influenced it and the (later) work it inspired. Universalists also argue that the return of any significant artifact or collection to its place of origin would create a slippery slope that would soon empty international museums of all their treasures, thereby denying potential visitors the chance of a universal encyclopedic experience.
Whatever the general merits and demerits of the universalist stance, it is short-sighted to appeal to it in the case at hand. At the New Acropolis Museum, we can explore the sculptures of the temple of the goddess Athena Parthenos within the rich cultural context of (i) the Pre-Classical (Archaic) Greek art and craft that influenced it – including prehistoric artefacts from as early as the Neolithic period, sculptures from the 8th Century BC temple of Athena Polias, and cult artefacts from the 6th Century BC sanctuary of the Nymphe; (ii) the near-contemporary monuments created for the same ground, namely the Propylaia (437-432 BC), the Temple of Athena Nike (c.426 BC), the Erektheion (421-406 BC) and the later sanctuaries of Dionysos Eleuthereus and Asklepios; and (iii) the Hellenistic (4th-1st Century BC) and Roman (1st-4th Century AD) work erected on the Acropolis, which includes two quadrigas with mythological compositions and royal statues. These important periods of development are all weakly represented in the British Museum, although it does house
one of the six Caryatids of the south side of the Erektheion (the other five remain in Athens). By contrast, the archeological excavation carried out at the site of the museum in Athens has recently unearthed thousands of additional finds from various phases of the ancient city, to be exhibited in 2010.If the missing sculptures and fragments were returned to Athens – be it on permanent loan or in exchange for some of the above – the museum would also allow visitors to study the sculptures of the single frieze, with its two pediments and 92 metopes, as one entire whole, naturally lit by the Attican sun, with a direct view of the monument of which they were once a part. Such an act of reunification would not set a precedent for any individual piece or collection that does not form an intricate part of a larger whole.
It is tempting to say that, by displaying them in sequence and in their entirety, we could get as close as possible to a true understanding of what the sculptor Phedias intended us to see. In actual fact we can already see much more than the ancients ever did, and not merely because only the very privileged few had access to it, whereas now anybody is free to enter, if not – regrettably – for free (as they are in the British Museum). The Ionic frieze originally occupied such a lofty position behind the outer Doric metopes that it could barely be observed. This is because the friezes were designed first and foremost to please not humans but the gods, a point easily forgotten in the New Museum, where we are also indulged with a 360% view of the finely sculpted pediment pieces, originally only subject to the judgment of human eyes from the front.
The British Museum responded to the opening of New Acropolis Museum by stating that the museum would consider temporary loan requests of their Parthenon sculptures by any foreign government, including Greece, provided that it was acknowledged that “the [British] museum has legal title” to the collection in question. The Greek minister of Culture, Antonis Samaras, expressed offence at the very thought of such a loan, since it impliedthat the sculptures were not owned by Greece: “How can anyone dare say they belong to the British?”. Asked whether the issue of ownership could be put aside, Samaras retorted that “no Greek can sign up for that”. Yet at this stage in history the question of ownership is of peripheral importance. If it turned out that the marble used to make the sculptures had been stolen from Persian quarries, would Samaras agree that the whole thing should be shipped to Iran? To put the question of ownership first is to let nationalistic sentiment obstruct the only path that makes aesthetic sense.
What has been worryingly clear for some time is that neither side in this debate cares about the sculptures for the right reasons. If they did, the removed sculptures would already be on display, for free, alongside the Athenian ones, be it on permanent loan/exchange from the British Museum – and from any other museums which hold pieces, such as the Louvre – or in a joint Greek and British international museum.
Constantine Sandis is a Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at Oxford Brookes University and New York University in London.
- British Museum refutes Parthenon Marbles loan reports : June 12, 2009
- A catalyst for the reunification of the Elgin Marbles : June 30, 2009
- Palermo fragment from Parthenon Marbles returns : October 5, 2008
- June opening date set for the New Acropolis Museum : February 14, 2009
- Seeing sculptures in a new light in the New Acropolis Museum : July 22, 2009
- Was an Elgin Marbles loan offer ever made? : June 12, 2009
- Talks planned between Greece & British Museum to discuss Parthenon Marbles : August 30, 2012
- UK representatives absent at New Acropolis Museum opening : June 20, 2009
DR.KWAME OPOKU said,
02.21.10 at 10:43 am
I am a bit surprised at the reasoning behind this argument:
“Yet at this stage in history the question of ownership is of peripheral importance. If it turned out that the marble used to make the sculptures had been stolen from Persian quarries, would Samaras agree that the whole thing should be shipped to Iran? To put the question of ownership first is to let nationalistic sentiment obstruct the only path that makes aesthetic sense.”
How can anybody dismiss as “peripheral” a dispute between two parties that has gone on for so long? What is “peripheral” is a question of perspective. To suggest that the dispute regarding the Parthenon/Elgin Marbles is peripheral involves a value judgment which anyone may make but can we substitute our value judgment for that of the parties involved who are at least in agreement that the question of ownership is important?
To suggest that the origin of the materials used in building the Parthenon Marbles would be determinative of the question of ownership is to introduce an element which will not help anyone in a dispute that one has, a priori determined to be “peripheral”. It also shows lack of familiarity with settlement of questions of ownership. The origin of materials used in creating a work of art or any object in dispute of ownership may not even be in itself the subject of contestation. We do not solve a dispute by substitution of a new issue which has not been raised by the parties. If this would work, we could solve existing disputes by declaring them “peripheral” and introducing other issues the parties may not have considered.
Consider the number of objects in Europe made of materials from Africa. Could one suggest that they all belong to Africa even if the materials were acquired through legal purchase from the owners? This reminds one of MacGregor’s argument that materials used in creating the Benin Bronzes came from Europe and that this justifies the retention of the looted artefacts by the British Museum
As for the idea that demands for the return of a cultural object are made for “nationalistic sentiment”, we should not be misled by the museum directors.
What about the retention of the object? Is that also motivated by “nationalist sentiment? Are the British Museum and its supporters in this matter any less nationalistic than the Greeks? Many of us believe that objects are better understood in their original context and support the United Nations and UNESCO in their efforts to assist in restitution of cultural objects that have been acquired under dubious circumstances. Are we all then nationalists, along with the archaeologists and others who take this view?
What does it mean to say that “What has been worryingly clear for some time is that neither side in this debate cares about the sculptures for the right reasons?”
What are the “right reasons”? Are those the “aesthetic” ones? Those reasons which have been developed hundred years after the objects have been taken from their original context and the holders have had enough time to find post facto justifications that obscure or modify the history of the acquisition and concentrate on the purely contemplation of the objects? Those holding the disputed objects then argue that the context or the location is no longer relevant. MacGregor has argued recently that the location of the Parthenon/Elgin Marbles was never an issue or is an issue of the past, what mattered now, he stated, was how the British and the Greeks can enable the Africans and Chinese to view the Parthenon Marbles! Do we need to say anything more on this way of arguing?
Kwame Opoku.